John Rawls and the Liberal Faith
by Peter Berkowitz
iberalism has always staked its claim to govern on its
superior rationality. The modern liberal tradition, with its
premise of the natural freedom and equality of all, arose in the
17th century partly in response to the turmoil of Europe's wars of
religion. When John Locke set out in his first Letter
concerning Toleration (1689) to demarcate the sphere of life
that belonged to religion and the sphere that belonged to secular
authorities, he relied on reason rather than religion to map the
boundaries. In the 18th and 19th centuries, in the writings of
Montesquieu, James Madison, John Stuart Mill, and others,
liberalism forged an alliance with the commercial spirit, science,
and democracy. These were the forces associated with progress,
while religion was generally equated with reaction. In the 20th
century, the liberal tradition faced the eruption of the forces of
unreason in hideous secular forms--Nazism and communism--and
defeated them. At the beginning of the 21st century, a threat to
the liberal tradition has erupted again, this time drawing
strength from religion.
Over the centuries,
however, the liberal tradition has also drawn strength from
religion. Locke viewed the law of reason--a moral law that he
regarded as universal and objective--as an expression of God's
eternal order. He also argued that religion, no less than reason,
taught toleration. In the 19th century, Alexis de Tocqueville
argued that liberal democracy in America depended on the vitality
of the people's religious faith. Hegel sought to show that the
liberal state is Christianity in secular and political form.
Today, even as the United States wages a worldwide war against
religiously inspired terrorism, religion remains a powerful force
within America itself.
|
et
at the heart of the liberal idea a question remains: Is it
reasonable for a liberal to be religious? Can it be reasonable to
claim to put freedom first while also binding oneself to a system
of theological notions about where we come from, what we are, and
how we ought to live? Such doubts have a distinguished pedigree in
the liberal tradition, and they have impelled many contemporary
liberals to regard religion with intense suspicion, if not
outright hostility.
In the old quarrel between liberalism and religion, John Rawls,
the preeminent academic moral philosopher of the last 50 years,
has often seemed to encourage the view that while liberals must
tolerate religious faith, it would be unreasonable for them to
profess it. But with the publication at the end of his career of
his Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy (2000),
Rawls's most searching examination of liberalism's foundations, he
provides reasons to believe that far from being the antithesis of
freedom, religious faith of a certain sort may be the basis of our
respect for freedom, the very thing that renders our respect
rational.
Rawls's Lectures is based on his notes for the class on
moral philosophy he taught at Harvard University between 1962 and
1991. As in all his writings, he gives pride of place in these
lectures to questions about moral reasoning. He is concerned above
all with the logic of morality, its presuppositions, its
principles, and the basic legal and political institutions that
flow from it. Rawls finds inspiration chiefly in the daunting
writings of the great 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel
Kant. He does discuss other thinkers. David Hume, with whom he
begins, raised the question that Kant attempted to resolve: How
can there be universal moral standards untainted by our passions
and interests? Part of Kant's answer is elaborated in the
Critique of Pure Reason (1781): The very structure of
reason, independent of our passions and interests, provides
universal standards. Another part is found in the Groundwork of
the Metaphysic of Morals (1785), The Critique of Practical
Reason (1788), and other works in which Kant develops the idea
from a variety of angles that the universal moral standard takes
the form of a law, the Categorical Imperative, which requires us
to act according to a maxim that we could will to be a universal
law. Rawls concludes with Hegel, who clarified, corrected, and
supplemented Kant. But, as in Rawls's other writings, Kant is the
looming philosophical presence.
Despite the title's suggestion that the book will be a
panoramic survey, Rawls turns in the Lectures to the
history of moral philosophy in the apparently narrow interest of
making sense of Kant. But he turns to Kant in order to make sense
of the moral life as it truly is. The implication is that the
history of moral philosophy culminates in Kant and more or less
comes to an end in the Kantian-inspired moral philosophy that
Rawls's own work exemplifies. What Rawls introduces as a
circumscribed scholarly effort to understand Kant is actually a
bold defense of the Kantian idea that the very essence of morality
consists in reasoning correctly on the basis of universal moral
laws.
|
n
intriguing mixture of circumspection and boldness has been a
leading trait of Rawls throughout his career. Colleagues and
students at Harvard marveled at the quiet and unassuming manner of
this man whose work his many admirers believe is likely to stand
alongside that of Kant, and Locke and Mill too, as a lasting
contribution to the liberal tradition. As a young assistant
professor in the early 1950s, Rawls was already devoting himself
to development of the ideas about freedom, equality, and justice
that would eventually establish him as the most influential
academic moral philosopher of his age. Yet he did not publish his
first book, the seminal A Theory of Justice, until 1971,
when he was 50. His second book, Political Liberalism, born
as a response to criticisms directed at his first, did not appear
until 1993, two years after Rawls had retired. In 1999, when he
was 78, he published two more books. The Law of Peoples is
a compact volume in which he develops a liberal theory of
international law and foreign policy. In the massive Collected
Papers he gathers together the vast majority of his published
scholarly articles, virtually every one an occasion to elaborate
or modify his interpretation of the moral and political
imperatives of liberalism. In Justice as Fairness: A
Restatement (2001), Rawls seeks to provide a final, unified
statement of his ideas. But it is in Lectures on the History of
Moral Philosophy, a work composed, in effect, over the entire
span of his career, that Rawls provides the most sustained and
provocative exploration of the theoretical foundations of his
liberalism.
A Theory of Justice, 20 years in the making, was
immediately hailed as a classic. Not only was it the defining work
of Rawls's career, but it also set the agenda for an entire
generation of moral philosophers and political theorists. In 600
highly theoretical, closely argued pages, Rawls sought to show
that a distinctive conception of justice is implicit in relatively
simple human "intuitions," and that it has definite implications
for constitutional law and the basic organization of political
institutions.
The well-ordered state that emerges from Rawls's prodigious
philosophical labors is nothing very novel, especially for the
professors who have always been his chief audience. It is the
familiar modern progressive welfare state, which seeks to protect
individual liberty while redistributing wealth in the name of
social and economic equality. What makes A Theory of
Justice distinctive is the complex conceptual machinery Rawls
assembles in making his case. But what is truly remarkable, when
you step back and think about it, is Rawls's crowning contention
that a certain interpretation of left-liberal politics is not only
right and good and in accord with our intuitions--all partisans
see their own positions that way--but that such a politics is
nothing less than an imperative of reason--objective, universal,
and, when all is said and done, binding on everybody.
The key device Rawls uses to derive all of this from our
intuitions is what he calls the "original position." Think of it
as a modern version of the early liberal thinkers' "state of
nature." It is a purely hypothetical state or condition that Rawls
constructs in order to determine what choices about basic
principles a perfectly reasonable person would make if asked to
design a society from scratch. In order to guarantee their
reasonableness, Rawls puts his hypothetical subjects behind a
"veil of ignorance." The veil of ignorance removes from their
sight the attributes that distinguish them from other human
beings. They are stripped of information about what is given to
them in particular by society and what is given to them in
particular by nature and fortune. To ensure that their choice of
fair principles for social cooperation is not influenced by
morally irrelevant factors, they are deprived of knowledge of
family and friends, social class and political opinions, nation
and religious beliefs, height and weight and sex, and whether they
are healthy, wealthy, or wise. Nevertheless, they know that in the
society they design, they will share four traits with all other
human beings: desires that require the cooperation of others to
satisfy; rationality, which enables choice among different ends; a
sense of justice; and a capacity to formulate ideas about what is
good. This is the "original position."
According to A Theory of Justice, anyone in the original
position would rationally choose to live under a conception of
justice founded on two principles. The first principle provides
that "each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive
basic liberty compatible with a similar liberty for others." This
principle has priority; it cannot be violated, even in the name of
the other. The second, the so-called difference principle,
stipulates that "social and economic inequality are to be arranged
so that they are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone's
advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all."
These principles, formed by reasoning in the original position,
represent an interpretation of the moral and political
significance of the freedom and equality of persons.
When it comes to the relation between reason and morality, A
Theory of Justice suffers from a fundamental ambiguity. Rawls
himself sometimes notes, but obscures by endless restatement and
qualification, that the original position is not a point of
departure for discovering morality's premises so much as a
formulation of them and a means for sketching out some of their
most basic practical implications. The veil of ignorance is not a
device for deriving morality: It already reflects an
interpretation of what is and what is not morally relevant for
politics. Because it takes a strong stand on the essence of
morality, presupposing that what is morally worthy in human beings
is their elemental freedom and equality--and not, for example,
particular passions and virtues such as courage and self-control,
or practical attachments and achievements such as friendship and
family--the original position is moral through and through. And
controversial.
At the same time, to make the case that it would be rational to
choose his two principles--which in significant measure define the
essential features of progressive politics in America--Rawls must
introduce assumptions about human nature that are not secured by
reason. They are based instead on his understanding of human
psychology. He assumes, for example, that people are fundamentally
risk averse. Placed in the original position, they would not
gamble on principles that might allow them to come out far ahead
of others. Instead, they would choose principles of justice that
provide the highest possible standard for the minimal conditions
under which society would allow anyone to live. Why? Because they
might be forced to live under those conditions themselves.
The obfuscations that underlie the relation between reason and
morality in Rawls's theory encourage an unlovely tendency--which
ripens in the thought of his disciples--to regard anybody who does
not share the enthusiasm for an energetically redistributive
liberalism as more than mistaken. By cloaking its political
conclusions in the mantle of disinterested and universal reason,
A Theory of Justice insinuates that many opinions heard in
public debate--on welfare reform, on abortion, on affirmative
action--don't deserve a place at the table. They are, in this
view, unreasonable. Such a view can all too easily feed the
illiberal conviction that left-wing progressives are separated
from centrists and right-wing conservatives not just by opinions
(over which reasonable people can disagree) but by a gulf akin to
the one that separates civilized people from philistines and
barbarians.
In Political Liberalism, Rawls tried to allay the
concerns of those--particularly communitarians--who found that the
conception of liberalism he had developed in A Theory of
Justice went too far, making comprehensive claims about
morality and politics that failed to respect the limits of reason
and the value of tradition and faith. Rawls responded with a line
of argument that seemed to meet his critics halfway. He implicitly
acknowledged defects they attributed to his argument, but he said
they were defects that were not essential to his conception. His
brand of liberalism, he argued, did not depend on comprehensive
moral claims or controversial first principles, and did not
forsake the shared values and actual agreements of people living
in today's liberal democracies. But by insisting in Political
Liberalism that his liberalism could be understood as
"political, not metaphysical," Rawls exacerbated the confusion
about the relation between reason and morality inhering in A
Theory of Justice.
The key concept in Political Liberalism is "the idea of
public reason." This is the reason, or that part of reason, that
should govern citizens of a liberal democracy in deliberating
about constitutional essentials and questions of basic justice. It
is based on the idea of the "reasonable." People are reasonable by
virtue of "their willingness to propose and abide by fair terms of
social cooperation among equals," which requires "their
willingness to accept the consequences of the burdens of judgment"
(i.e., they recognize that citizens inevitably will come to
different conclusions about important moral and political
questions). While few readers would quarrel with Rawls's
definition of what is reasonable, it is odd for him to suggest
that qualities that have built into them the idea that consent and
fairness and equality are good things are not at the same time
essentially moral, and therefore entangled with opinions about
metaphysics and first principles.
|
he
idea of public reason is not a correction of the confusion found
in A Theory of Justice; it is only a more subtle version of
it. This reluctance to state clearly liberalism's dependence on
morality and metaphysics would be nothing more than an eccentric
intellectual tic were it not that this obfuscation reflects, and
provides continuing cover for, the unlovely tendency to advance
one's own partisan political judgments as if they flow from
impartial reason. Taking one's stand with reason rather than
morality--especially a "reason" into which considerable moral and
political content has already been poured--is a way of being
judgmental without getting personal or political, of seeming to
remain above the partisan fray.
In a long footnote in Political Liberalism, Rawls
himself demonstrates how easy it is to abuse the idea of public
reason by peremptorily conferring its prestige on quite debatable
moral and political judgments. The footnote deals with the issue
of abortion, and Rawls assumes "three important political values:
the due respect for human life, the ordered reproduction of
political society over time, including the family in some form,
and finally the equality of women as equal citizens." But in the
very effort to show the real-life operation of public reason, he
dispenses with argument and instead offers authority:
Now I believe any reasonable balance of these three values will
give a woman a duly qualified right to decide whether or not to
end her pregnancy during the first trimester. The reason for this
is that at this early stage of pregnancy the political value of
the equality of women is overriding, and this right is required to
give it substance and force. Other political values, if tallied
in, would not, I think, affect this conclusion.
Note well what Rawls says on this formidable issue, and the
ease with which he says it. Public reason, as Rawls wields it,
goes well beyond providing the ground rules for debate between
pro-choice and pro-life forces. It proclaims that the pro-life
view is unwelcome in public debate because it does not acknowledge
public reason's minimal determination: "At this early stage of
pregnancy the political value of the equality of women is
overriding." And Rawls thinks it enough to assure the reader that
public reason declares all of this without examining the key
competing "political value," due respect for human life in the
form of the life of the fetus or unborn child.
It is sobering to observe that even in the hands of a careful
and high-minded thinker such as Rawls, the appeal to public reason
can serve to highhandedly deny the reality of competing goods and
tragic choices and intractable questions--to disguise, in other
words, reason's limits. The master's lapse dramatizes how readily
partisan intellectuals might arrogate public reason and, thus
armed, use it in the heat of public debate to dispense with
reason, cut off discussion, shut down questioning, and stop the
inquiring mind dead in its tracks.
In The Law of Peoples, Rawls revisits the question of
public reason, but he only compounds the confusion. He reiterates
the claim that public reason is political rather than
metaphysical--that it has nothing to do with controversial beliefs
about human nature and comprehensive moral, philosophical, and
religious conceptions. Yet he holds that public reason specifies
"equal basic rights and liberties for all citizens"--which sounds
a lot like a moral claim with metaphysical roots, even if it's one
that virtually all Americans would endorse.
The confusion is compounded in other ways. To avoid, under the
guidance of public reason, the making of universal, comprehensive
claims, political liberals "seek a shareable public basis of
justification for citizens in society." Yet political liberalism's
very quest for laws and institutions that can in principle be
shared by and justified to all is motivated by the sort of
universal, comprehensive claims--about freedom and equality and
what it means to treat people fairly--that it earnestly forswears
and says, for the record, that it does without. And so on. The
consistency in his confusions suggests that the idea of public
reason answers a need that arises within Rawls's thinking to hide
his universalism while extending it to cover all peoples.
|
n
the interpretation of Kant in Lectures on the History of Moral
Philosophy, Rawls's inability to decide whether liberalism's
moral foundations are secured by reason comes most clearly to
light. On the one hand, he emphasizes the centrality to Kant's
philosophy of "the fact of reason." As Rawls explains it, this is
"the fact that, as reasonable beings, we are conscious of the
moral law as the supremely authoritative and regulative law for us
and in our ordinary moral thought and judgment we recognize it as
such." In other words, the very operation of reason compels us to
accept the moral law. But on the other hand, Rawls stresses Kant's
view that the moral law only achieves its full significance and
justification in the spirit of religious faith:
I conclude by observing that significance Kant gives
to the moral law and our acting from it has an obvious religious
aspect, and that his text occasionally has a devotional
character.
What gives a view a religious aspect, I think, is that it has
a conception of the world as a whole that presents it as in
certain respects holy, or else as worthy of devotion and
reverence. The everyday values of secular life must take a
secondary place. If this is right, then what gives Kant's view a
religious aspect is the dominant place he gives to the moral law
in conceiving of the world itself. For it is in following the
moral law as it applies to us, and in striving to fashion in
ourselves a firm good will, and in shaping our social world
accordingly that alone qualifies us to be the final purpose of
creation. Without this, our life, in the world, and the world
itself lose their meaning and point.
Now, perhaps, we see the significance of the mention of the
world in the first sentence of Groundwork I: "It is impossible
to conceive anything in the world, or even out of it, that can
be taken as good without qualification, except a good will."
At first it seems strange that Kant should mention the world
here. Why go to such an extreme? we ask. Now perhaps we see why
it is there. It comes as no surprise, then, that in the second
Critique he should say that the step to religion is taken for
the sake of the highest good and to preserve our devotion to the
moral law.
These religious, even Pietist, aspects of Kant's moral
philosophy seem obvious; any account of it that overlooks them
misses much that is essential to it.
One is tempted to say of Rawls's philosophy what Rawls says of
Kant's philosophy. For both one must ask: How can the moral law be
both a fact of reason and in need of justification by faith?
Perhaps in the end it is less that Rawls is confused than that
his conscientious philosophical investigations lead him to keep
bumping up against fundamental tensions in the liberal spirit. And
these fundamental tensions shed light on conflicting qualities to
which the liberal spirit seems to give rise. On the one hand, for
example, an appreciation that the moral foundations of liberalism
are bound up with a faith in human dignity, a faith that is not
entailed or guaranteed by reason, may encourage a certain
humility, of the sort shown in toleration, in interest in the
variety of ways of being human, and in skepticism about
comprehensive claims. On the other hand, the conviction that the
founding truths of liberalism, as well as the more contingent
policies and political institutions a person may prefer, are
implicit in common sense may promote a certain hubris. It is this
hubris that one sees in the bullying, blustering attitude of
people who are secure in the knowledge that those who disagree
with them on social and political matters suffer from wicked or
twisted minds. Contemporary liberals do not have a monopoly on
humility or on hubris. But the ascendancy of one or the other of
these qualities in the liberal spirit may make the difference
between a liberalism that knows its limits and a liberalism that
knows no limits.
In an instructive phrase in the Lectures, Rawls says
that Kant's moral philosophy aspires to the ideal of an
"aristocracy of all." This calls to mind John Stuart Mill's vision
of a society of sovereign individuals, as well as the Protestant
notion of a "priesthood of all believers." All three notions are
variations on a venerable modern theme: the harmonization of a
substantial human equality with a sweeping individual freedom. It
is not hard to understand the aspiration to an aristocracy of all.
But can a person's human desire for distinction be satisfied in a
society in which everybody is recognized as an aristocrat,
sovereign, or priest? What are the practical effects on our hearts
and minds of the conviction that each person is supreme? And what
are the implications for moral psychology, or how the moral life
is actually lived, of a form of moral reasoning that authorizes
all individuals to conceive of themselves as laying down universal
laws? These are some of the intriguing questions--seldom raised by
his colleagues and students--that Rawls's probing classroom
lectures ought to provoke among those who wish to assess the
reasonableness of Rawlsian liberalism.
|
n
the universities, at a time when most philosophy professors were
engaged in dry-as-dust conceptual analysis, John Rawls gave new
life to a certain progressive interpretation of classical
liberalism. His philosophical labors, which were devoted to
clarifying the structure of liberal thought, brought to light, in
some cases unwittingly, stresses and strains, fissures and flaws,
and ironic twists and turns in the liberal spirit. Nowhere was
this more true than in relation to liberalism's foundations.
Rawls's thinking culminated with a series of books in which he
defended the idea of a "political conception of justice." This was
supposed to be a free-standing liberalism, a liberalism resting
solely on Americans' shared intuitions about freedom and equality.
From these shared intuitions, Rawls tried to derive fair terms of
social cooperation, the constitutional ground rules under which it
would be reasonable for free and equal citizens to choose to live.
But is the intuition that we are free and equal a freestanding
truth of reason? Or is it a belief that is also nurtured by
religious faith? While many of Rawls's followers regard it as bad
manners (at best) to raise such a question, we now know, thanks to
his recently published lectures, that Rawls himself raised the
question and saw something serious at stake in how it was
answered.
In trying to come to grips with the foundations of liberalism,
Rawls offers conflicting ideas. On the one hand, he holds that the
founding moral intuitions are self-evident. On the other, he holds
that they rest on faith. Yet if good arguments can be made on
behalf of both propositions, then by definition the moral
intuitions cannot be self-evident. What is evident is the doubt
about how precisely to understand liberalism's moral foundations.
So at minimum it is reasonable to pursue the fecund thought that
Rawls's freestanding liberalism actually stands on an act of
faith. Perhaps Rawls's conflicting accounts can be reconciled, as
in the Declaration of Independence, through the idea that a
certain faith impels us to hold as self-evident the truth that all
people are by nature free and equal.
No one is saying that liberalism requires you to be religious
or that religious people are more amply endowed with the liberal
spirit. But for those who care about understanding liberalism, a
more precise knowledge of its foundations should be welcome. And
as a practical matter, for those who care about freedom and
equality, knowledge of the foundations of the truths we have long
held to be self-evident can contribute to our ability to cultivate
the conditions under which we can keep our grip on them firm.
Reprinted from the Spring 2002 Wilson
Quarterly
This article may not be resold, reprinted, or redistributed
for compensation of any kind without prior written permission from
the author. For further reprint information, please contact
Permissions, The Wilson Quarterly, One Woodrow Wilson
Plaza, 1300 Pennsylvania Avenue, NW, Washington, D.C. 20004-3027
(202-691-4200).
|
|